THE "OPENNESS" OF GOD:
A REPLY TO WILLIAM HASKER
Christian Scholar's Review
28 (1998): 124-133.
Alfred J. Freddoso
University of Notre Dame
1. Introduction
Emulating Bill Hasker, I will begin with a few autobiographical remarks.
Numbered among the half-dozen or so writers whom I have been most influenced
by spiritually as well as intellectually are St. Augustine of Hippo and
St. Thomas Aquinas. Having pondered at length the philosophical doctrines
of God fashioned by these two brilliant and holy men, I find it difficult
to entertain the idea that we moderns will be better positioned philosophically
to make progress in our understanding of the divine nature once we set
aside their principal metaphysical claims. Yet the authors of The Openness
of God1 urge me not only to entertain this idea
but to embrace it wholeheartedly. Again, having tasted of the spiritual
riches contained in the extensive Biblical commentaries of St. Augustine
and St. Thomas, I find it difficult to believe that we moderns will be
better positioned theologically to make progress in our understanding of
the Scriptural portrayal of God once we recognize that these commentaries
and others like them are tainted with philosophical elements contrary to
the Christian Faith. Yet this is what the authors of The Openness of
God ask me to believe.
What's more, even though Hasker and the others impugn many of the attributes
that enter into the traditional conception of God--to wit, simplicity,
immutability, impassibility, eternality, total sovereignty, comprehensive
knowledge of the future, particular providence2--the
book does not contain (and, as far as I can tell, does not pretend to contain)
any new arguments against these attributes. Instead, drawing from a wide
array of extant sources, including their own previous work, the authors
try to undermine the traditional conception of God by alluding to, and
sometimes giving brief renditions of, a number of familiar objections to
the attributes in /125/ question. Since I have never been convinced by
these objections taken one by one, I am pretty much unmoved by their all
being piled on top of one another within a single volume.
So despite the laudable intention of the authors to help us improve
our understanding of God, I must confess to certain misgivings about their
project. Still, I have greatly benefitted from the exercise of trying to
turn my visceral reaction to this provocative book into an articulate response
to the challenge it lays down. My hope is that others, the authors among
them, might derive some corresponding benefit from the results of that
exercise.
2. The book as a whole: style and intended audience
Though I will concentrate mainly on Hasker's own chapter, entitled "A
Philosophical Perspective," I want to begin with a comment about the style
and intended audience of the book as a whole, since the book's genre renders
certain types of criticisms inappropriate.
As I understand it, The Openness of God is not meant to be a
scholarly treatise on the concept of God; nor is it aimed exclusively or
even primarily at an academic audience. Instead, it reads more like a thoughtful
exhortation--a meditative manifesto, if you will--that briefly spells out
the main contours of the 'open' conception of God and provides an outline
of the sort of historical, philosophical, and theological considerations
that can be mustered in its defense. The book's principal aim, it appears,
is to win the initial sympathy of educated Christians and to lure the scholars
among us into adopting as our own the research program it recommends.
If this assessment is correct, it seems unbecoming to take the authors
to task for their lack of thoroughness. So, for instance, critics should
not fuss about the fact that the chapter entitled "Historical Considerations"
dispatches with Calvin in a little over two pages, Luther in a little over
one page, and Thomas Aquinas in a little under one page. Nor should they
linger over the fact that the authors have not given a suitably exhaustive
reply to the problem of prophecy, or over the fact that Hasker has still
not made clear exactly why the 'open' God, who is after all very knowledgeable
about human behavior, /126/ as well as very powerful, fares better than
the "self-contained God of the classical tradition" (pp. 126-127) when
it comes to reconciling moral atrocities with divine providence.3
Again, it would be out of place to fret over the rhetorical excesses the
authors indulge in.
How, then, should one reply? In broad strokes, to be sure. But where
should the focus be? There are many inviting issues, but I will limit myself
to two. First, I will raise some questions about Hasker's contention that
we contemporary Christian thinkers have a philosophical advantage over
our classical predecessors when it comes to fashioning an accurate conception
of God. Second, taking my cue from Douglas Kelly's contribution to the
Christianity
Today symposium on the book,4 and with St. Thomas
as my guide, I will argue that the authors of The Openness of God
owe us a philosophically rigorous account of God's transcendence.
3. Their metaphysical predispositions versus ours
How could the Fathers of the Church and other classical Christian thinkers
have gone so wrong with regard to the concept of God? And how is it that
the authors of The Openness of God have managed to succeed where
their classical predecessors, many saints among them, failed? We can glean
Hasker's reply from various remarks he makes in his own chapter of the
book. Let's begin with the following passage:
"Without a doubt a very large number of philosophical
issues are involved in the difference between the divine openness view
and the classical conception of God--far too many to discuss in a single
chapter. My task is made somewhat easier, however, by the fact that many
of the inclinations and preconceptions with which we today approach these
issues are decidedly different from those which prevailed when the theological
tradition was being formed. To be sure, the fact that a view was once widely
held and has now been generally abandoned is not a decisive reason to reject
it; truths can be forgotten and then rediscovered. But when we are assessing
the merits of views supported by a long tradition, it is surely appropriate
to consider the ways in which the assumptions that influenced the shaping
of the tradition differ from our own" (p. 127).
Hasker then notes the pervasive influence of neo-Platonism on many classical
Christian thinkers, an influence embodied (as he sees it) in their nearly
unanimous bias in favor of the doctrines of divine simplicity, eternality,
immutability, and impassibility. By contrast, our own inclinations carry
us moderns in just the opposite direction. Take, for instance, the specific
case of immutability:
"In the philosophical lineage stretching from Parmenides
to Plato to Plotinus, there is a strong metaphysical and valuational preference
for permanence over change .... And this bias against change has been powerfully
influential in classical theology, leading to the insistence on an excessively
strong doctrine of divine immutability .... For us moderns, this preference
for permanence over change is scarcely compelling. Indeed, it is arguable
that in our intellectual life as well as in our general culture the pendulum
has swung too far in /128/ the other direction, so that if anything at
all remains constant for a while our response is one of boredom and impatience.
Be that as it may, the extreme valuational preference for immutability
has little hold on our thinking, and the appeal of theological doctrines
based on this valuation is weakened accordingly" (p. 129).
The idea, broadly stated, is this: Christian thinkers toil within concrete
cultural and intellectual contexts, and these contexts instill in them
cognitive predispositions which, though defeasible, nonetheless serve as
tacit measures of plausibility. Since the contexts within which we contemporary
philosophers operate are quite different from those within which classical
Christian thinkers operated, it is not surprising that our cognitive predispositions
should diverge substantially from theirs. More specifically, given the
striking contrast in style and content between the analytic metaphysical
tradition in which many of us have been trained and the Greek metaphysical
traditions into which classical Christian thinkers were initiated, our
metaphysical predispositions can be expected to differ dramatically from
theirs.
When we turn to the task of fashioning a Christian conception of God
from the resources afforded us by reason and revelation, this difference
turns out to be especially crucial. For, as Hasker sees it, in carrying
out this task, orthodox Christian thinkers are all engaged in so-called
'perfect being theology', which, he tells us, "is operative, both explicitly
and implicitly, at many, many points in the theological tradition" (p.
131). That is, we begin from the presupposition that God is an absolutely
perfect being--a presupposition Hasker willingly embraces--and then we
proceed to determine just which attributes are to count as divine perfections.
Some attributes are relatively uncontroversial, but the traditional "metaphysical"
attributes mentioned above are not among them. As Hasker puts it, "I do
not think it should be taken as obvious, without long and thoughtful consideration,
that it is 'better' for God to be temporal or timeless, mutable
or immutable, passible or impassible" (p. 132). And it is
precisely with regard to these abstract and esoteric attributes that the
above-noted difference in metaphysical predispositions has its greatest
impact.
I will return below to the claim that classical Christian thinkers were
all engaged in 'perfect being theology'; let us assume for now that they
were so engaged. According to Hasker, their judgments about what constitutes
perfection were unduly influenced by cognitive predispositions instilled
by the now defunct neo-Platonic metaphysical tradition; we, on the other
hand, are in a position to correct their mistakes and thus to rescue the
Biblical portrayal of God from an outmoded metaphysics that forces us to
interpret an excessively large part of that portrayal as metaphorical rather
than literal. In short, having been freed from classical metaphysical prejudices,
we can--and should--be true to our own metaphysical predispositions:
"It is in the end out of the question for anyone to 'prove'
that a particular conception of God is the correct one. Rather, one simply
finds that a particular way of understanding the things of God makes the
most sense, and provides the greatest illumination, in the overall context
of one's thinking and living. And so we offer a challenge to the reader,
to 'try and see' whether he or she cannot find a rich and satisfying understanding
of Scripture, of the Christian faith generally and of our life in Christ,
seen through the lens of the openness of God" (p. 154). /128/
Several questions come immediately to mind, but I will raise just two of
them. First, and most obviously, how have our metaphysical predispositions
been formed? It has been fewer than four decades since analytic metaphysics
re-emerged from the shadow of positivism and ordinary language philosophy,
two of the most virulently anti-metaphysical movements in the history of
philosophy. Even counting the earlier achievements of the likes of Frege
and Russell, analytic metaphysics is thus in its embryonic stage, judged
by the standard of the two thousand year tradition that ran from Plato
to Suarez and into early modern philosophy. Moreover, we have still not
recovered fully from the disdain for the history of metaphysics that marked
graduate training in philosophy during the middle decades of this century.
The result is that very few of us analytic metaphysicians received in graduate
school any deep or systematic introduction to the history of our own discipline,
especially the history of ancient and medieval metaphysics. And the resulting
historical blindness helps explain why in many cases we have become "locked
in" to ways of formulating metaphysical problems and of defining possible
solutions to those problems that we are well-nigh incapable of recognizing
as contingent and, I would add, highly questionable.
Here are some examples. Nearly all analytic treatments of causality
take it for granted that events, rather than stable entities, are the relata
of the basic causal relation. Again, nearly all analytic treatments of
action take it for granted that if the concepts action, power,
and agent causality have any application at all, they are applicable
only in the case of free and rational beings. Yet only a handful of pre-Humean
philosophers, most notably the occasionalists, would have had even the
slightest inclination to accept either of these assumptions. Again, analytic
philosophers of mind almost unanimously assume that Cartesian dualism is
the only remotely plausible non-materialistic solution to the mind-body
problem; and given the historically conditioned patterns of thought with
which we have become comfortable, even the few of us who have heard of
the Aristotelian alternative are as likely as not to pronounce it unintelligible.
This historical illiteracy is especially disheartening in analytic philosophy
of religion, where ignorance of, or spotty acquaintance with, medieval
metaphysics effectively cuts us off from the most comprehensive and penetrating
reflection on the Christian Faith that has occurred in the history of the
Church. And here, too, even those of us, myself included, who do, as it
were, "dip into" the history of philosophical theology very often succumb
to the temptation to force classical concepts and theories into the straitjacket
of currently fashionable modes of thinking.
The most striking example is the contemporary literature on divine simplicity.
Hasker tells us that "a strong majority of Christian philosophers" (p.
127) have abandoned the doctrine of divine simplicity; I submit that a
"strong majority" of contemporary Christian philosophers do not so much
as understand the doctrine of divine simplicity or the metaphysical background
from which it emerged. In an important recent paper Nicholas Wolterstorff
traces the futility of the contemporary discussion of simplicity to a largely
unnoticed difference between styles /129/ of ontology--more specifically,
between what he calls the "constituent ontology" characteristic of medieval
metaphysicians and the "relation ontology" that marks contemporary analytic
metaphysics.5 And while Wolterstorff himself is no
friend of either constituent ontology or the doctrine of God that historically
developed from it, he nonetheless recognizes that a convincing case for
rejecting the medieval tradition in philosophical theology can be made
only from within by philosophers who understand deeply what they are rejecting.6
From these considerations I draw two conclusions. First, without the
sort of systematic study that we are not generally trained for either linguistically
or philosophically, we contemporary Christian philosophers are not in a
position even to understand, much less to criticize intelligently, most
of the work of those classical metaphysicians whom Hasker takes to task.
For in order to grasp what these authors are saying, we must immerse ourselves
in their works and, at least initially, humbly submit ourselves to their
tutleage; but this is a project that most of us have neither the expertise
nor the time nor the inclination to undertake. Second, given the realities
of our peculiar historical situation, we have no good reason to believe
that, with respect to the conception of God, the metaphysical predispositions
engendered by contemporary culture and philosophical training are more
reliable than those of the classical Christian thinkers.
The second question I wish to raise concerns the advice that we "try
and see" whether the 'open' conception of God works for us. Hasker's discussion
of the parable of the Prodigal Son in the present paper is meant as a test
case. Ask yourself: "Would the parable be as gripping if we imagined the
father to be immutable and impassible, or to have comprehensive knowledge
of the future?" I think we can agree that it would not be as gripping.
But exactly why not? Well, to begin with, it is no perfection for a human
father to be immovable and impassible concerning the fate of his own children--just
the opposite, in fact. If the father in the parable were not anxious and
yet hopeful, he wouldn't be a very good father. Nor is it a human perfection
to be omniscient, even though we can at least recognize omniscience as
the limiting case of something that is a genuine human perfection.
But what conclusion should we draw from this? Hasker invites us to conclude
that if the traditional conception of God is correct, then the parable
of the Prodigal Son is at least in part misleading, since it portrays the
father as having certain traits which are of central importance to the
story and yet which a divine being could not possibly have. And, indeed,
if all we knew about God were what philosophers ignorant of Christian revelation
have been able to tell us, it would be very hard to recognize God in the
father of the parable; to put it another way, it would be very /129/ hard
to swallow the idea that if God were somehow to become human, he would
be anything like the father of the parable (see 1 Corinthians 1:18-25).
(Of course, if all we knew about God were what he had revealed of himself
to Moses and the prophets, we would be astonished by the very suggestion
that the transcendent bearer of the ineffable name of Exodus 3 might somehow
become human--once again, see 1 Corinthians 1:18-25.)
Yet as Christians, illumined by divine revelation concerning the mysteries
of the Trinity and the Incarnation, we have a pretty good idea of what
our transcendent God would be like as a human being--namely, exactly like
Jesus Christ, who dined with public sinners, thus exciting the murmurs
that prompted the parable of the Prodigal Son. According to the traditional
Christian understanding of God, it is precisely in the person of our Lord
Jesus Christ that the impassible, immutable, eternal God becomes passible,
mutable, and time-bound. We Christians don't need to invent an 'open' conception
of the divine nature in order to marvel at the "folly" of a risk-taking,
passible God; all we need to do is to contemplate Christ crucified.7
Perhaps Hasker will retort that if we understand the divine nature in
the traditional way, then it is impossible that any person should be both
divine and human. But, as far as I can tell, the doctrine of the Incarnation
would seem no less a folly to unbelieving metaphysicians if the 'open'
conception of the divine nature were substituted for the traditional conception.
After all, even according to the 'open' conception, God is an omnipotent
and omniscient Creator, an immaterial, imperfectible, and transcendent
Being without beginning or end. What's more, the strategies available to
Hasker and the others for countering the objection that no being can be
both God (conceived of as 'open') and man will be just those strategies
that classical Christian thinkers have employed to fend off the parallel
objection to the thesis that Jesus Christ is both God (conceived of in
the traditional way) and man. In a nutshell, as long as we stop short of
reducing the divine nature to a merely human nature, the familiar metaphysical
objections to the doctrine of the Incarnation will continue to arise, and
the methods for dealing with those objections will continue to be the same.
On this score, then, the traditional and 'open' conceptions of God are
on a par. Still--or so it seems to me--the traditional conception
of God at least yields the spiritual benefit of emphasizing in excelsis
the truly awe-inspiring character of the Incarnation and of the subsequent
divine invitation to us to rise above the status of servile creatures ("I
no longer call you slaves") and to become, literally, the sons and daughters
of the utterly transcendent Creator who is, mirabile dictu, our
heavenly Father as well. /131/
4. Thomas Aquinas and divine transcendence
I want to close with a few remarks about the method by which St. Thomas
arrives at his philosophical conception of the divine nature--remarks prompted
both by Hasker's claim that the classical theologians were engaged in 'perfect
being theology' and by Douglas Kelly's charge that the authors of The
Openness of God "have failed to think through the profound implications
of the difference between created being and uncreated being."8
St. Thomas's reflections on the divine nature can be divided into three
phases: (1) the proof of the existence of a First Efficient Cause, i.e.,
a being which acts and is a cause of other things but is not itself caused
or acted upon;9 (2) the via remotionis, in
which the First Cause is divided off from all other entities by denying
of it various intrinisic modes of being and composition characteristic
of created entities; and (3) the via affirmationis, in which positive
perfections are attributed to the First Cause. (This triadic structure
is clearly evident in Summa Contra Gentiles I, chaps. 10-102, but
can also be discerned in Summa Theologiae I, qq. 2-26.)
Significantly, the thesis that the First Cause is a perfect being is
the conclusion of Phase 2 rather than an initial assumption. It is only
in Phase 3--the via affirmationis--that we see anything resembling
'perfect being theology'. Yet several of the attributes impugned by Hasker--to
wit, eternality, immutability, impassibility, and simplicity--are 'negative'
attributes argued for in Phase 2, that is, before 'perfect being
theology' kicks in. So, at least in the case of St. Thomas, Hasker's remarks
about the classical predispositions in favor of these four attributes are
beside the point. St. Thomas is not judging on the basis of cognitive predispositions
that these attributes, in contradistinction to their opposites, bespeak
perfection. Rather, he is arguing--and the arguments are many and diverse--that
these attributes follow from the concept First Efficient Cause (or,
in the end, Creator), under which God's existence was proved in
Phase 1.
Let me expound on this just a bit. St. Thomas claims, pace St.
Anselm, that in natural theology we do not begin with a direct positive
(or 'quidditative') concept of God--that is, a concept which would allow
us to situate the divine nature within a taxonomy of genera and species
and thus to initiate a systematic inquiry into its positive properties.
Instead, we are forced to reason discursively from certain evident features
of the sensible world to the existence of a First Efficient Cause of those
features, and then to argue from the descriptive concept First Efficient
Cause to the conclusion that the being whose existence has been proved
must be radically different intriniscally from the ordinary sensible entities
that we do have direct positive concepts of. The upshot of this via
remotionis is that the First /131/ Cause is "perfect in every way".10
It is only afterwards--in Phase 3--that we try to isolate a set of pure
perfections which, if abstracted from the restrictive conditions under
which they occur in creatures, can be attributed literally, albeit analogically,
to the Creator.
In effect, then, the via remotionis constitutes an inquiry into
the difference between Creator and creature. And within St. Thomas's system
a being capable of creating ex nihilo is ultimately characterized
in two basic and, as I have argued elsewhere,11
complementary ways, one stemming from the Aristotelian tradition (Pure
Actuality) and the other stemming from the Platonic tradition (Unparticipated
Being). Within their respective traditions, these are limiting notions
which strain our cognitive and imaginative resources but which for that
very reason provide us with a powerful characterization of the ontological
abyss that divides the transcendent Creator of all things from the entities
he creates. In the Thomistic system, then, there is no doubt about the
utter "otherness," incomprehensibility, and ineffability of the divine
nature.
By contrast, even though the authors of The Openness of God affirm
God's transcendence, they have not as yet provided any correspondingly
forceful metaphysical account of that transcendence. Unlike St. Thomas,
they have given us no principled explanation of what sort of being is capable
of creating ex nihilo, or of how such a being differs in its inner
nature from created beings.
Why is this a serious omission? As indicated above, a metaphysical conception
of the divine nature helps us divide the Scriptural descriptions of God
into the literal and the metaphorical. The authors of The Openness of
God object to the division made on the basis of the traditional conception
of God; in particular, they claim that many Scriptural descriptions of
God are unjustifiably classified as metaphorical by appeal to the negative
properties (immutability, eternality, impassibility, simplicity) constitutive
of the classical notion of divine transcendence. However, it is not at
all clear on what basis the authors are making their own division
into the literal and the metaphorical. Why, for instance, do they cling
to the idea that God is immaterial and thereby relegate a whole host of
Scriptural descriptions of God to the realm of the metaphorical, given
that immateriality is just another one of those 'Hellenistic' divine attributes
that has little appeal for the modern mind? The authors insist, after all,
that God has genuine emotions, and many of us who reject Cartesian dualism
think that in the case of human beings certain bodily changes are essential
to the having of emotions properly so-called. What makes the authors think
that this is not true in the case of God as well? One might even perversely
suggest that the "whole emotional content" of the parable of the Prodigal
Son is "profoundly altered" if we imagine that the father, because he has
no body, is unable literally to embrace his son or to share the fatted
calf with him. /132/
What standard, then, are Hasker and the others invoking in the case
of immateriality? More generally, what full-fledged alternative to the
traditional account of transcendence can they offer us? I suggest that
they put the formulation of such an account at or near the top of their
agenda as they continue to develop their research program.
NOTES
1. The Openness of God: A Biblical Challenge
to the Traditional Understanding of God, by Clark Pinnock, Richard
Rice, John Sanders, William Hasker, and David Basinger (Downers Grove,
IL: InterVarsity Press, 1994). In what follows all page references are
to this book.
2. It is perhaps worthwhile to note in passing
that, within my own Catholic tradition, the attributes impugned in the
Openness
of God have been affirmed not only by the most eminent theologians
but also by the Church herself. The two most important councils in this
regard are Lateran IV (1215) and Vatican I (1869-70), though one finds
explicit mention of all these attributes in official ecclesiastical documents
dating from the first few centuries of the history of the Church. For instance,
eternality is affirmed in the ancient creed Quicumque, simplicity
and immutability (and, by implication, impassibility) are affirmed by Pope
St. Leo the Great in letters that date from the middle of the fifth century.
3. Accordingly, I will not repeat here my objections
to the account of God's knowledge and providence that is contained in Hasker's
God,
Time and Knowledge (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1989). See
my review of this book
in Faith and Philosophy 8 (1993): 99-107.
4. Christianity Today, January 9, 1995,
30-34.
5. Nicholas Wolterstorff, "Divine Simplicity,"
Philosophical
Perspectives 5 (1991): 531-552.
6. On a personal note, I myself have over the years
come to believe rather firmly in the superiority of constituent ontology
to relation ontology. For interested beginners in this area, I have made
available on the World Wide Web (/courses/courses.htm)
a number of class handouts for courses dealing with scholastic philosophy,
including a brief introduction
to scholastic ontology.
7. Richard Rice tries to turn this argument on
its head by claiming, in effect, that Jesus could not be passible as a
human being unless the divine nature were antecedently passible (see pp.
45-46). But his main argument for this claim is summed up in the contention
that "the cross is nothing less than the suffering of God." Since any alert
Christian proponent of the traditional conception of God will accept this
premise while denying the conclusion that the divine nature is passible,
it seems that at least one further premise is needed.
8. "Afraid of Infinitude," Christianity Today,
January 9, 1995, 32.
9. Strictly speaking, what the argument shows,
if successful, is that each being and each change is such that it has a
First Efficient Cause. It is only later, in Phase 3, that St. Thomas argues
that there is just a single First Efficient Cause of all beings and changes.
However, I will ignore this complication in what follows.
10. Summa Contra Gentiles I, chap. 28.
11. "God's
General Concurrence with Secondary Causes: Why Conservation is Not Enough,"
Philosophical
Perspectives 5 (1991): 553-585, esp. 561-563. |